University of St Andrews AHCR web site CSMN web site
 
 
The Arché Weblog
 
 
 

Basic Knowledge Workshop: Call For Graduate Papers

Tuesday, March 28, 2006

An Arché workshop on Basic Knowledge will take place on 24-25 November 2006. Speakers will include Jason Stanley, Duncan Pritchard, Jessica Brown and Timothy Williamson. There will be a slot for a graduate student paper. Graduate students, and those who obtained their PhDs within the last twelve months, are invited to submit papers of not more than 5000 words. Please send submissions as email attachments in Word or similar format (no pdf files please) to Carrie Jenkins. Suitable topics include: Sceptical Paradox, Transmission and/or Closure, Non-Evidential Warrant, Internalism and Externalism, and A Priori Knowledge. Particularly welcome are papers which open up new areas of enquiry within these fields, and/or highlight directions in which further research is needed. Travel and subsistence will be covered by Arche for the author of the selected paper.
 

Status Belli

Friday, March 17, 2006

The final Arché Abstraction Workshop, informally titled 'Status Belli', will take place in St Andrews on 8-10 December. Details will be posted on TWiki as they become available.
 

What Price Bivalence?

Monday, March 13, 2006

In a talk I've been giving various places recently, I've argued that Delia Graff's theory of vagueness, like other theories which hold onto bivalence, runs into trouble with the forced-march Sorites. Here's the worry in brief. Graff explains our ignorance of where the boundary in a given series lies with the following similarity constraint:

'..if two things are saliently similar [in the relevant respect], then it cannot be that one is in the extension of a vague predicate, or in its anti-extension, while the other is not.' (2000: 57)

The idea is that whenever one is evaluting a pair of items in a suitably constructed Sorites series, both will be saliently similar, and so either both are in the extension of the predicate in question or both are in the anti-extension; the boundary is never where we are looking for it. This also gives an explanation of why we are liable to find Sorites reasoning compelling despite its invalidity (something critics have complained is entirely missing from Williamson-brand Epistemicism, though it's a central concern in Sorensen's Vagueness and Contradiction).

But now imagine a subject shown the items in a Sorites series in order, and asked of each whether it is in the extension of the relevant predicate or the anti-extension. Given the way the series has been constructed, she can neither competently judge all of the items to be in the extension, nor all of the items to be in the anti-extension. So at some point she must 'jump'; that is, judge some item n to be in the extension, yet judge item n + 1 (differing only marginally in the relevant respects from n) to be in the anti-extension. But by the similarity constraint, the boundary in known not to lie between n and n + 1, so how can her judgements be viewed as competent?

As Derek Ball, Geoff Georgi and Crispin Wright all rightly pointed out to me in various discussions, Graff has an answer to that question ready. It's essentially that of Diana Raffman in 'Vagueness without Paradox' (1994); when the subject judges n to be in the extension, n + 1 is too, but when the subject jumps, the boundary shifts so that now both n and n + 1 are in the anti-extension. So the subject's judgements can be seen as competent, yet the similarity constraint is never violated. As Raffman writes (1994: 57):

'There are shifts - events that occur - but these are best viewed as Gestalt like changes of ‚Äúperspective‚ÄĚ or ‚Äúanchor,‚ÄĚ not as boundary crossings - at least not if by ‚Äėboundary‚Äô you mean something that installs a simultaneous and/or fixed category difference between adjacent patches.'

It's clear that my original objection fails to engage with this kind of response, but I've been wondering how it's actually meant to work, given Graff's committment to bivalence - I've reached the conclusion that it doesn't. In presenting the forced-march above, I assumed that the subject only had two available responses. But we should be able to drop this assumption and allow the subject to respond as she likes (see for example Raffman 1994: 45-6). Suppose the subject judges n to be in the extension; then n + 1 is also in the extension. Now suppose when confronted with n + 1, the subjects responds 'I don't know', or 'There's no fact of the matter', or 'It's neither in the extension nor the anti-extension'. How does a shift in the location of the boundary such that both items are now in the anti-extension help to ensure that the subject says something competent? The problem is this; the boundary is supposed to shift so as to accomodate the speakers judgements - that's how we can see the subject who jumps in the face of the forced-march as doing something competent - but while there are a number of judgements a subject might return, the endorser of bivalence only recognises binary options for accomodating them.

(In a recent Analysis note ('How to understand contextualism about vagueness', 2005) Raffman explicitly considers what would happen on her earlier view when a subject switches from judging items to lie in the extension of the relevant predicate to judging them to be borderline. But the issues I raise above don't get into sight, simply because in a parenthetical remark she assumes '[f]or the sake of argument only' that we're working in a three-valued logic (246). With the assumption in place the subject's judgements can be accomodated, but that doesn't help us see how the trick is to be pulled whilst retaining bivalence.)
 

Grundgesetze Translation Project website

Sunday, March 12, 2006

The Grundgesetze Translation Project website is online now.

Go to the Arché website and click on "Projects" in the column on the left hand side to find it.
 

Executive Directorship Available

Friday, March 10, 2006

Anyone who wants my job can now read the advertisement for it at jobs.ac.uk.
 

Arche papers online

Wednesday, March 08, 2006

Just an announcement: many of Crispin Wright's papers are now available online, from the 'outcomes' section of the Arche website. These pages also have links to many other online papers, including work in progress. (Arche members/associates/network members: if you would like your work to be included, just send me a link or a file!)
 

Could a priori knowledge be subject-sensitive?

Friday, March 03, 2006

Here's a question that arose out of reading Thomas Crisp's recent Analysis note, 'Hawthorne on Knowledge and Practical Reasoning'.

According to Delia Graff's theory of vagueness ('Shifting Sands', 2000), contextualism gets something important wrong, and something important right. Contra the contextualist, vague predicates like 'heap' and 'bald' express the same property throughout their respective suitably constructed Sorites series. Yet changes in the practical interests of a subject making judgements with such predicates determine shifts in their extensions (shifts not attributable to changes in the relevant comparison class, etc), and the resulting picture of the semantics of such expressions i. invalidates Sorites reasoning, ii. explains why we find such reasoning intuitively compelling, and iii. does not require us to give up classical logic or semantics. So the contextualist has something like the right idea, but the hope is Graff's theory delivers the same package whilst neatly avoiding some familiar problems with contextualist approaches.

Now, while the extension of a vague predicate is sensitive to the practical interests of the relevant subject, there are restrictions on such boundary-shifting; just as admissible sharpenings for a supervaluationist must respect the clear polar cases, Graff suggests that on her view the interests of a subject can never determine that the boundary shifts so that, to take an extreme case, a man with no hairs on his head is in the anti-extension of 'bald'. There's something very reasonable about this requirement, but last summer I remember Carrie, Robbie, and other people around the Vagueness project wondering whether Graff really needs or is entitled to it.

Crisp's note suggested to me that there might be a similar issue for interest-relative invariantism (IRI) about knowledge, as defended in Hawthorne and Stanley's recent monographs. According to IRI, contextualism about knowledge gets something important wrong, and something important right. Contra the contextualist, the property expressed in knowledge ascriptions is invariant. Yet changes in the practical interests of a subject determine shifts in whether or not their true beliefs count as knowledge (even keeping their evidence fixed). So whether or not a subject's true belief counts as knowledge depends on non-epistemic (at least as traditionally conceived) features of their circumstances, such as how high the stakes are regarding the possibility that they're wrong.

The parallel question to the one we might want to ask the boundary-shifter about vagueness is this; could it ever be the case that the consequences of being wrong about the truth of a proposition are so disasterous that knowledge attributions are defeated, despite the proposition enjoying some (putatively) priviledged epistemic status (apriority or analyticity, for example)? Crisp's paper suggests that without some Chisholming, Hawthorne's formulation of IRI does indeed allow this possibility. Is there a neat way to avoid such a committment, or is it just a consequence of IRI (unless we do some special-pleading regarding a priori knowledge)? If it is a genuine committment, is that a particuarly bad result? There certainly seems something somewhat counter-intuitive about it, but are there materials for an objection?